paper/src/paper.tex
author Eugen Sawin <sawine@me73.com>
Wed, 29 Jun 2011 18:39:07 +0200
changeset 19 241e7ad6593c
parent 18 ebda6a5fc738
child 20 3402f14d907a
permissions -rw-r--r--
Layout and stuff.
sawine@7
     1
\documentclass[a4paper, pagesize, DIV=calc, smallheadings]{article}  
sawine@2
     2
\usepackage{graphicx}
sawine@2
     3
%\usepackage[latin1]{inputenc}
sawine@14
     4
\usepackage{amsmath, amsthm, amssymb, amsfonts, verbatim}
sawine@2
     5
\usepackage{typearea}
sawine@2
     6
\usepackage{algorithm}
sawine@2
     7
\usepackage{algorithmic}
sawine@15
     8
\usepackage{multicol}
sawine@11
     9
%\usepackage{fullpage}
sawine@19
    10
%\usepackage{a4wide}
sawine@19
    11
\usepackage[left=3.9cm, right=3.9cm]{geometry}
sawine@5
    12
%\usepackage[T1]{fontenc}
sawine@5
    13
%\usepackage{arev}
sawine@7
    14
%\pagestyle{headings}
sawine@19
    15
sawine@2
    16
\renewcommand{\familydefault}{\sfdefault}
sawine@17
    17
\newcommand{\M}{\mathcal{M}}
sawine@17
    18
\newcommand{\N}{\mathbb{N}_0}
sawine@19
    19
\newcommand{\F}{\mathcal{F}}
sawine@19
    20
\newcommand{\Prop}{\mathcal{P}}
sawine@19
    21
sawine@7
    22
\title{\uppercase{\textbf{\Large{A}\large{lgorithmic} \Large{V}\large{erification of} \Large{R}\large{eactive} \Large{S}\large{ystems}}\\
sawine@7
    23
\tiny{Draft}
sawine@7
    24
}}
sawine@7
    25
\author{
sawine@19
    26
\uppercase{{\small{E}\scriptsize{UGEN} \small{S}\scriptsize{AWIN}}\thanks{\lowercase{\scriptsize{\texttt{sawine@informatik.uni-freiburg.de}}}}\\
sawine@19
    27
{\em \small{U}\scriptsize{NIVERSITY OF} \small{F}\scriptsize{REIBURG}}\thanks{\tiny{Computer Science Department, Research Group for Foundations of Artificial Intelligence}}\\
sawine@7
    28
%{\em \small{C}\scriptsize{omputer} \small{S}\scriptsize{cience} \small{D}\scriptsize{epartment}}\\
sawine@7
    29
{\em \small{G}\scriptsize{ERMANY}}}\\
sawine@7
    30
%\texttt{\footnotesize{sawine@informatik.uni-freiburg.de}}
sawine@7
    31
}
sawine@5
    32
\date{\textsc{\hfill}}
sawine@7
    33
sawine@15
    34
\theoremstyle{definition} %plain, definition, remark, proposition, proof, corrolary
sawine@7
    35
\newtheorem*{def:finite words}{Finite words}
sawine@7
    36
\newtheorem*{def:infinite words}{Infinite words}
sawine@8
    37
\newtheorem*{def:regular languages}{Regular languages}
sawine@8
    38
\newtheorem*{def:regular languages closure}{Regular closure}
sawine@7
    39
\newtheorem*{def:omega regular languages}{$\omega$-regular languages}
sawine@8
    40
\newtheorem*{def:omega regular languages closure}{$\omega$-regular closure}
sawine@11
    41
\newtheorem*{def:buechi automata}{Automata}
sawine@11
    42
\newtheorem*{def:automata runs}{Runs}
sawine@11
    43
\newtheorem*{def:automata acceptance}{Acceptance}
sawine@14
    44
\newtheorem*{def:vocabulary}{Vocabulary}
sawine@19
    45
\newtheorem*{def:frames}{Frames}
sawine@18
    46
\newtheorem*{def:models}{Models}
sawine@18
    47
\newtheorem*{def:satisfiability}{Satisfiability}
sawine@14
    48
sawine@15
    49
\theoremstyle{proposition}
sawine@14
    50
\newtheorem{prop:vocabulary sat}{Proposition}
sawine@15
    51
sawine@0
    52
\begin{document}
sawine@0
    53
\maketitle
sawine@4
    54
\thispagestyle{empty}
sawine@2
    55
%\itshape
sawine@2
    56
%\renewcommand\abstractname{Abstract} 
sawine@0
    57
\begin{abstract}
sawine@0
    58
Over the past two decades, temporal logic has become a very basic tool for spec-
sawine@0
    59
ifying properties of reactive systems. For finite-state systems, it is possible to use
sawine@0
    60
techniques based on B\"uchi automata to verify if a system meets its specifications.
sawine@0
    61
This is done by synthesizing an automaton which generates all possible models of
sawine@0
    62
the given specification and then verifying if the given system refines this most gen-
sawine@0
    63
eral automaton. In these notes, we present a self-contained introduction to the basic
sawine@0
    64
techniques used for this automated verification. We also describe some recent space-
sawine@0
    65
efficient techniques which work on-the-fly.
sawine@0
    66
\end{abstract}
sawine@2
    67
%\normalfont
sawine@4
    68
\newpage
sawine@2
    69
\section{Introduction}
sawine@2
    70
Program verification is a fundamental area of study in computer science. The broad goal
sawine@5
    71
is to verify whether a program is ``correct''--i.e., whether the implementation of a program
sawine@2
    72
meets its specification. This is, in general, too ambitious a goal and several assumptions
sawine@2
    73
have to be made in order to render the problem tractable. In these lectures, we will focus
sawine@2
    74
on the verification of finite-state reactive programs. For specifying properties of programs,
sawine@2
    75
we use linear time temporal logic.
sawine@2
    76
sawine@2
    77
What is a reactive program? The general pattern along which a conventional program
sawine@2
    78
executes is the following: it accepts an input, performs some computation, and yields an
sawine@2
    79
output. Thus, such a program can be viewed as an abstract function from an input domain
sawine@2
    80
to an output domain whose behaviour consists of a transformation from initial states to
sawine@2
    81
final states.
sawine@2
    82
sawine@2
    83
In contrast, a reactive program is not expected to terminate. As the name suggests, such
sawine@2
    84
systems “react” to their environment on a continuous basis, responding appropriately to
sawine@2
    85
each input. Examples of such systems include operating systems, schedulers, discrete-event
sawine@2
    86
controllers etc. (Often, reactive systems are complex distributed programs, so concurrency
sawine@2
    87
also has to be taken into account. We will not stress on this aspect in these lectures—we
sawine@2
    88
take the view that a run of a distributed system can be represented as a sequence, by
sawine@2
    89
arbitrarily interleaving concurrent actions.)
sawine@2
    90
sawine@2
    91
To specify the behaviour of a reactive system, we need a mechanism for talking about
sawine@2
    92
the way the system evolves along potentially infinite computations. Temporal logic 
sawine@2
    93
has become a well-established formalism for this purpose. Many varieties of temporal logic
sawine@2
    94
have been defined in the past twenty years—we focus on propositional linear time temporal
sawine@2
    95
logic (LTL).
sawine@2
    96
sawine@2
    97
There is an intimate connection between models of LTL formulas and languages of
sawine@2
    98
infinite words—the models of an LTL formula constitute an ω-regular language over an
sawine@2
    99
appropriate alphabet. As a result, the satisfiability problem for LTL reduces to checking
sawine@2
   100
for emptiness of ω-regular languages. This connection was first explicitly pointed out in.
sawine@2
   101
sawine@8
   102
\section{$\omega$-regular languages}
sawine@7
   103
\begin{def:finite words}
sawine@11
   104
Let $\Sigma$ be a non-empty set of symbols, called the alphabet. $\Sigma^*$ is the set of all \emph{finite} words over $\Sigma$. A \emph{finite} word $w \in \Sigma^*$ is a \emph{finite} sequence $v_0,...,v_{n-1}$ of symbols from alphabet $\Sigma$ with length $n = |w|$. $\varepsilon$ denotes the empty word with length $|\varepsilon| = 0$.
sawine@7
   105
\end{def:finite words}
sawine@7
   106
sawine@8
   107
\begin{def:regular languages}
sawine@8
   108
The class of regular languages is defined recursively over an alphabet $\Sigma$:
sawine@15
   109
\begin{multicols}{2}
sawine@8
   110
\begin{itemize}
sawine@8
   111
\item $\emptyset$ is regular
sawine@8
   112
\item $\{\varepsilon\}$ is regular
sawine@8
   113
\item $\forall_{a \in \Sigma}:\{a\}$ is regular
sawine@8
   114
\end{itemize}
sawine@15
   115
\end{multicols}
sawine@8
   116
\end{def:regular languages}
sawine@8
   117
sawine@8
   118
\begin{def:regular languages closure}
sawine@10
   119
Let $L_{R_1}, L_{R_2} \in \Sigma^*$ be regular. The class of regular languages is closed under following operations:
sawine@15
   120
\begin{multicols}{2}
sawine@8
   121
\begin{itemize}
sawine@8
   122
\item $L_{R_1}^*$
sawine@8
   123
\item $L_{R_1} \circ L_{R_2}$
sawine@8
   124
\item $L_{R_1} \cup L_{R_2}$
sawine@10
   125
\item $L_{R_1} \cap L_{R_2}$
sawine@10
   126
\item $\overline{L}_{R_1}$ and therefore $L_{R_1} - L_{R_2}$
sawine@8
   127
\end{itemize}
sawine@15
   128
\end{multicols}
sawine@8
   129
\end{def:regular languages closure}
sawine@8
   130
sawine@9
   131
\begin{def:infinite words}
sawine@17
   132
$\Sigma^\omega$ is the set of all \emph{infinite} words over $\Sigma$. An \emph{infinite} word $w \in \Sigma^\omega$ is an \emph{infinite} sequence $v_0,...,v_\infty$ with length $\infty$. To address the elements of the infinite sequence $w$, we view the word as a function $w : \N \to \Sigma$ with $w(i) = v_i$; thus $w(i)$ denotes the symbol at sequence position $i$ of word $w$; another notation used for $w(i)$ is $w_i$.
sawine@9
   133
\end{def:infinite words}
sawine@9
   134
sawine@7
   135
\begin{def:omega regular languages}
sawine@8
   136
Set $L$ is an $\omega$-language over alphabet $\Sigma$ iff $L \subseteq \Sigma^\omega$. Let $L_R \subseteq \Sigma^*$ be a non-empty regular finite language and $\varepsilon \notin L_R$. A set $L$ is $\omega$-regular iff $L$ is an $\omega$-language and $L = L_R^\omega$.
sawine@7
   137
\end{def:omega regular languages}
sawine@7
   138
sawine@8
   139
\begin{def:omega regular languages closure}
sawine@8
   140
Let $L_{\omega_1}, L_{\omega_2} \subseteq \Sigma^\omega$ be $\omega$-regular languages. The class of $\omega$-regular languages is closed under following operations:
sawine@8
   141
\begin{itemize}
sawine@8
   142
\item $L_R \circ L_{\omega_1}$, but \emph{not} $L_{\omega_1} \circ L_R$
sawine@8
   143
\item $L_{\omega_1} \cup L_{\omega_2}$, but only \emph{finitely} many times
sawine@8
   144
\end{itemize}
sawine@8
   145
\end{def:omega regular languages closure}
sawine@7
   146
sawine@8
   147
\section{B\"uchi automata}
sawine@11
   148
\begin{def:buechi automata}
sawine@15
   149
A non-deterministic B\"uchi automaton is a tuple $A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$, where $\Sigma$ is a finite non-empty \emph{alphabet}, $S$ is a finite non-empty set of \emph{states}, $S_0 \subseteq S$ is the set of \emph{initial states}, $F \subseteq S$ is the set of \emph{accepting states} and $\Delta: S \times \Sigma \times S$ is a \emph{transition relation}. When suitable we will use the arrow notation for the transitions, where $s \xrightarrow{a} s'$ iff $(s, a, s') \in \Delta$.
sawine@11
   150
sawine@11
   151
A deterministic B\"uchi automaton is a specialisation where the \emph{transition relation} $\Delta$ is a \emph{transition function} $\delta: S \times \Sigma \to S$ and the set $S_0$ of \emph{initial states} contains only a single state $s_0$.
sawine@11
   152
sawine@19
   153
Within this text \emph{automaton} will refer to the non-deterministic B\"uchi automaton, unless otherwise noted. 
sawine@11
   154
\end{def:buechi automata}
sawine@11
   155
sawine@11
   156
\begin{def:automata runs}
sawine@17
   157
Let $A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$ be an automaton, a run $\rho$ of $A$ on an infinite word $w = a_0,a_1,...$ over alphabet $\Sigma$ is a sequence $\rho = s_0,s_1,...$, where $s_0 \in S_0$ and $(s_i, a_i, s_{i+1}) \in \Delta$, for all $i \geq 0$. Again we may view the run sequence as a function $\rho : \N \to S$, where $\rho(i) = s_i$ denotes the state at the $i^{th}$ sequence position.
sawine@11
   158
\end{def:automata runs}
sawine@11
   159
sawine@11
   160
\begin{def:automata acceptance}
sawine@17
   161
Let $A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$ be an automaton and let $\rho$ be a run of $A$, we define $inf(\rho) = \{s \in S \mid \exists^\omega{n \in \N}: \rho(n) = s\}$, where $\exists^\omega$ denotes the existential quantifier for infinitely many occurances, i.e., $s$ occurs infinitely often in $\rho$.
sawine@11
   162
sawine@15
   163
The run $\rho$ is \emph{accepting} iff $inf(\rho) \cap F \neq \emptyset$, i.e., there exists an \emph{accepting state} which occurs infinitely often in the run $\rho$. The automaton $A$ \emph{accepts} an input word $w$, iff there exists a run $\rho$ of $A$ on $w$, such that $\rho$ is \emph{accepting}. The language $L_\omega(A)$ recognised by automaton $A$ is the set of all infinite words accepted by $A$.
sawine@11
   164
\end{def:automata acceptance}
sawine@11
   165
sawine@8
   166
\section{Linear temporal logic}
sawine@19
   167
\subsection{Syntax}
sawine@19
   168
Let $\Prop$ be the countable set of \emph{atomic propositions}. The \emph{alphabet} of the language $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$ is $\Prop \cup \{\neg, \lor, X, U\}$. We define the $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$-\emph{formulae} $\varphi$ using following productions:
sawine@19
   169
\[\varphi ::= p \in \Prop \,|\, \neg \varphi \,|\, \varphi \lor \varphi \,|\, X \varphi \,|\, \varphi U \varphi\]
sawine@13
   170
sawine@18
   171
\subsection{Interpretation}
sawine@13
   172
The intuition should go as follows: $\neg$ and $\lor$ correspond to the Boolean \emph{negation} and \emph{disjunction}, the unary temporal operator $X$ reads as \emph{next} and the binary temporal operator $U$ reads as \emph{until}.
sawine@13
   173
sawine@13
   174
LTL is interpreted over \emph{computation paths}, where a computation corrensponds to a model over a \emph{Kripke-frame} constructed by the order of natural numbers.
sawine@13
   175
sawine@18
   176
\subsection{Semantics}
sawine@19
   177
\begin{def:frames}
sawine@19
   178
A LTL-\emph{frame} is a tuple $\F = (S, R)$, where $S = \{s_i \mid i \in \N\}$ is the set of states and $R = \{(s_i, s_{i+1}) \mid i \in \N\}$ the set of accessibility relations. Hence $S$ is an isomorphism of $\N$ and $R$ an isomorphism of the strict linear order $(\N, <)$, which corresponds to the linear progression of time. 
sawine@19
   179
\end{def:frames}
sawine@19
   180
sawine@18
   181
\begin{def:models}
sawine@19
   182
A LTL-\emph{model} is a tuple $\M = (\F, V)$, where $\F$ is a \emph{frame} and $V: S \to 2^\Prop$ a \emph{valuation function}. Intuitively we say $p \in \Prop$ is \emph{true} at time instant $i$ iff $p \in V(i)$. 
sawine@19
   183
%A \emph{model} is a function $\M: \N \to 2^\Prop$ over \emph{frame} $\F$. The frame constitutes a linear order over $\N$, which corresponds to the linear progression of time from the \emph{present/past} into the \emph{future}. Therefore $\M(i)$ assigns a set of \emph{positive atomic propositions} to each state of time instant $i$. Intuitively we say $p \in \Prop$ is \emph{true} at time instant $i$ iff $p \in \M(i)$.
sawine@18
   184
\end{def:models}
sawine@13
   185
sawine@18
   186
\begin{def:satisfiability}
sawine@19
   187
A model $\M = (\F, V)$ \emph{satisfies} a formula $\varphi$ at time instant $i$ is denoted by $\M,i \models \varphi$. Satisfiability of a formula $\varphi$ is defined inductively over the structure of $\varphi$:
sawine@13
   188
\begin{itemize}
sawine@19
   189
\item $\M,i \models p$ for $p \in \Prop$ iff $p \in V(i)$
sawine@17
   190
\item $\M,i \models \neg \varphi$ iff not $\M,i \models \varphi$
sawine@17
   191
\item $\M,i \models \varphi \lor \psi$ iff $\M,i \models \varphi$ or $\M,i \models \psi$
sawine@17
   192
\item $\M,i \models X \varphi$ iff $\M,i+1 \models \varphi$
sawine@17
   193
\item $\M,i \models \varphi U \psi$ iff $\exists{k \geq i}: \M,k \models \psi$ and $\forall{i \leq j < k}: \M,j \models\varphi$
sawine@13
   194
\end{itemize}
sawine@18
   195
\end{def:satisfiability}
sawine@18
   196
sawine@14
   197
\begin{def:vocabulary}
sawine@19
   198
Let $\varphi$ be a LTL-formula over atomic propositions $\Prop$, we define the \emph{vocabulary} $Voc(\varphi)$ of $\varphi$ inductively:
sawine@15
   199
\begin{multicols}{2}
sawine@14
   200
\begin{itemize}
sawine@19
   201
\item $Voc(p) = \{p\}$ for $p \in \Prop$
sawine@14
   202
\item $Voc(\neg \varphi) = Voc(\varphi)$
sawine@14
   203
\item $Voc(\varphi \lor \psi) = Voc(\varphi) \cup Voc(\psi)$
sawine@14
   204
\item $Voc(X \varphi) = Voc(\varphi)$
sawine@14
   205
\item $Voc(\varphi U \psi) = Voc(\varphi) \cup Voc(\psi)$
sawine@14
   206
\end{itemize}
sawine@15
   207
\end{multicols}
sawine@17
   208
%
sawine@17
   209
\noindent Let $\M$ be a model and $\varphi$ a LTL-formula, we define model $\M_{Voc(\varphi)}$:
sawine@17
   210
\[\forall{i \in \N}: \M_{Voc(\varphi)} = \M(i) \cap Voc(\varphi)\]
sawine@17
   211
\end{def:vocabulary}
sawine@17
   212
%
sawine@17
   213
\begin{prop:vocabulary sat}
sawine@17
   214
Let $\M$ be a model and $\varphi$ a LTL-formula, then following holds:
sawine@17
   215
\[\forall{i \in \N}: \M,i \models \varphi \iff \M_{Voc(\varphi)},i \models \varphi\] 
sawine@17
   216
\end{prop:vocabulary sat}
sawine@17
   217
%
sawine@19
   218
\subsection{Derived connectives}
sawine@17
   219
For a more convenient description of system specifications we present some derived symbols to be used in LTL-formulae. At first we introduce the notion of \emph{truth} and \emph{falsity} using constants $\top$ and $\bot$. Then we expand our set of connectives with the Boolean \emph{and}, \emph{implication} and \emph{equivalence}. And at last we derive the commonly used modal operators \emph{eventually} and \emph{henceforth}. 
sawine@15
   220
sawine@19
   221
Let $\varphi$ and $\psi$ be $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$-formulae:
sawine@15
   222
\begin{multicols}{2}
sawine@15
   223
\begin{itemize}
sawine@19
   224
\item $\top \equiv p \lor \neg p$ for $p \in \Prop$
sawine@15
   225
\item $\bot \equiv \neg \top$
sawine@15
   226
\item $\varphi \land \psi \equiv \neg (\neg \varphi \lor \neg \psi)$
sawine@15
   227
\item $\varphi \rightarrow \psi \equiv \neg \varphi \lor \psi$
sawine@15
   228
\item $\varphi \leftrightarrow \psi \equiv (\varphi \rightarrow \psi) \land (\psi \rightarrow \varphi)$
sawine@15
   229
\item $\Diamond \varphi \equiv \top U \varphi$
sawine@15
   230
\item $\Box \varphi \equiv \neg \Diamond \neg \varphi$
sawine@15
   231
\end{itemize}
sawine@15
   232
\end{multicols}
sawine@16
   233
From the derivations for operators $\Diamond$, \emph{read diamond}, and $\Box$, \emph{read box}, it follows:
sawine@17
   234
\begin{multicols}{2}
sawine@16
   235
\begin{itemize}
sawine@17
   236
\item $\M,i \models \Diamond \varphi$ iff $\exists{k \geq i}: \M,k \models \varphi$
sawine@17
   237
\item $\M,i \models \Box \varphi$ iff $\forall{k \geq i}: \M,k \models \varphi$
sawine@16
   238
\end{itemize}
sawine@17
   239
\end{multicols}
sawine@19
   240
sawine@19
   241
With the additional derived connectives we get the following $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$-formulae productions:
sawine@19
   242
\[\varphi ::= p \in \Prop \,|\, \neg \varphi \,|\, \varphi \lor \varphi \,|\, \varphi \land \varphi \,|\, X \varphi \,|\, \varphi U \varphi \,|\, \varphi \rightarrow \varphi \,|\, \varphi \leftrightarrow \varphi \,|\, \Diamond \varphi \,|\, \Box \varphi\]
sawine@19
   243
sawine@8
   244
\section{Model checking}
sawine@15
   245
sawine@19
   246
sawine@19
   247
\section{On-the-fly methods}
sawine@19
   248
sawine@0
   249
\begin{thebibliography}{99}
sawine@5
   250
\bibitem{ref:ltl&büchi} 
sawine@6
   251
\uppercase{M{\footnotesize adhavan} M{\footnotesize ukund}.}
sawine@5
   252
{\em Linear-Time Temporal Logic and B\"uchi Automata}.
sawine@2
   253
Winter School on Logic and Computer Science, Indian Statistical Institute, Calcutta, 1997.
sawine@0
   254
sawine@2
   255
\bibitem{ref:handbook} 
sawine@6
   256
\uppercase{P{\footnotesize atrick} B{\footnotesize lackburn}, 
sawine@6
   257
F{\footnotesize rank} W{\footnotesize olter and} J{\footnotesize ohan van} B{\footnotesize enthem}.}
sawine@2
   258
{\em Handbook of Modal Logic (Studies in Logic and Practical Reasoning)}.
sawine@3
   259
3rd Edition, Elsevier, Amsterdam, 2007.
sawine@7
   260
sawine@19
   261
\bibitem{ref:alternating verification} 
sawine@19
   262
\uppercase{M{\footnotesize oshe} Y. V{\footnotesize ardi}.}
sawine@19
   263
{\em Alternating Automata and Program Verification}.
sawine@19
   264
Computer Science Today, Volume 1000 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1995.
sawine@19
   265
sawine@7
   266
\bibitem{ref:infpaths}
sawine@7
   267
\uppercase{P{\footnotesize ierre} W{\footnotesize olper}, 
sawine@7
   268
M{\footnotesize oshe} Y. V{\footnotesize ardi and}
sawine@7
   269
A. P{\footnotesize rasad} S{\footnotesize istla}.}
sawine@7
   270
{\em Reasoning about Infinite Computation Paths}.
sawine@7
   271
In Proceedings of the 24th IEEE FOCS, 1983.
sawine@7
   272
sawine@0
   273
\end{thebibliography}
sawine@0
   274
\end{document}