paper/src/paper.tex
author Eugen Sawin <sawine@me73.com>
Fri, 15 Jul 2011 20:07:34 +0200
changeset 50 82c3364b42b5
parent 49 8e48b5f173ac
child 51 2d2ac8ba3a37
permissions -rw-r--r--
Automaton example.
     1 \documentclass[a4paper, pagesize, DIV=calc, smallheadings]{article}  
     2 \usepackage{graphicx}
     3 %\usepackage[latin1]{inputenc}
     4 \usepackage{amsmath, amsthm, amssymb, amsfonts, verbatim}
     5 \usepackage{typearea}
     6 \usepackage{algorithm}
     7 \usepackage{algorithmic}
     8 \usepackage{multicol}
     9 \usepackage{tikz}
    10 \usetikzlibrary{automata}
    11 \usepackage{sidecap}
    12 \usepackage{wrapfig}
    13 %\usepackage{fullpage}
    14 %\usepackage{a4wide}
    15 \usepackage[left=3.9cm, right=3.9cm]{geometry}
    16 %\usepackage[T1]{fontenc}
    17 %\usepackage{arev}
    18 %\pagestyle{headings}
    19 
    20 \floatname{algorithm}{Function}
    21 \renewcommand{\algorithmicrequire}{\textbf{Input:}}
    22 \renewcommand{\algorithmicensure}{\textbf{Output:}}
    23 
    24 \renewcommand{\familydefault}{\sfdefault}
    25 \renewenvironment{proof}{{\bfseries Proof.}}{}
    26 \newcommand{\M}{\mathcal{M}}
    27 \newcommand{\N}{\mathbb{N}_0}
    28 \newcommand{\F}{\mathcal{F}}
    29 \newcommand{\Prop}{\mathcal{P}}
    30 \newcommand{\A}{\mathcal{A}}
    31 \newcommand{\X}{\mathcal{X}}
    32 \newcommand{\U}{\mathcal{U}}
    33 \newcommand{\V}{\mathcal{V}}
    34 \newcommand{\dnf}{\mathsf{dnf}}
    35 \newcommand{\consq}{\mathsf{consq}}
    36 
    37 \title{\uppercase{\textbf{\Large{A}\large{lgorithmic} \Large{V}\large{erification of} \Large{R}\large{eactive} \Large{S}\large{ystems}}\\
    38 \tiny{Draft}
    39 }}
    40 \author{
    41 \uppercase{{\small{E}\scriptsize{UGEN} \small{S}\scriptsize{AWIN}}}\thanks{\texttt{sawine@informatik.uni-freiburg.de}}\\
    42 \uppercase{{\em \small{U}\scriptsize{NIVERSITY OF} \small{F}\scriptsize{REIBURG}}}\thanks{Computer Science Department, Research Group for Foundations of Artificial Intelligence}\\
    43 %{\em \small{C}\scriptsize{omputer} \small{S}\scriptsize{cience} \small{D}\scriptsize{epartment}}\\
    44 \uppercase{{\em \small{G}\scriptsize{ERMANY}}}\\
    45 %\texttt{\footnotesize{sawine@informatik.uni-freiburg.de}}
    46 }
    47 \date{\textsc{\hfill}}
    48 
    49 \theoremstyle{definition} %plain, definition, remark, proof, corollary
    50 \newtheorem*{def:finite words}{Finite words}
    51 \newtheorem*{def:infinite words}{Infinite words}
    52 \newtheorem*{def:regular languages}{Regular languages}
    53 \newtheorem*{def:regular languages closure}{Regular closure}
    54 \newtheorem*{def:omega regular languages}{$\omega$-regular languages}
    55 \newtheorem*{def:omega regular languages closure}{$\omega$-regular closure}
    56 \newtheorem*{def:buechi automata}{Automata}
    57 \newtheorem*{def:automata runs}{Runs}
    58 \newtheorem*{def:automata acceptance}{Acceptance}
    59 \newtheorem*{def:general automata}{Generalised automata}
    60 \newtheorem*{def:general acceptance}{Acceptance}
    61 \newtheorem*{def:vocabulary}{Vocabulary}
    62 \newtheorem*{def:frames}{Frames}
    63 \newtheorem*{def:models}{Models}
    64 \newtheorem*{def:satisfiability}{Satisfiability}
    65 \newtheorem*{def:fs closure}{Closure}
    66 \newtheorem*{def:atoms}{Atoms}
    67 \newtheorem*{def:rep function}{Representation function}
    68 \newtheorem*{def:next}{Next function}
    69 \newtheorem*{def:dnf}{Disjunctive normal form}
    70 \newtheorem*{def:positive formulae}{Positive formulae}
    71 \newtheorem*{def:consq}{Logical consequences}
    72 \newtheorem*{def:partial automata}{Partial automata}
    73 
    74 \theoremstyle{plain}
    75 \newtheorem{prop:vocabulary sat}{Proposition}[section]
    76 \newtheorem{prop:general equiv}{Proposition}[section]
    77 \newtheorem{prop:computation set=language}{Proposition}[section]
    78 
    79 \theoremstyle{plain}
    80 \newtheorem{thm:model language}{Theorem}[section]
    81 \newtheorem{cor:mod=model language}{Corollary}[thm:model language]
    82 \newtheorem{cor:mod=program language}[cor:mod=model language]{Corollary}
    83 \newtheorem{thm:model checking}{Theorem}[section]
    84 \newtheorem{lem:dnf}{Lemma}[section]
    85 \newtheorem{lem:consq}[lem:dnf]{Lemma}
    86 
    87 \begin{document}
    88 \maketitle
    89 \thispagestyle{empty}
    90 %\itshape
    91 %\renewcommand\abstractname{Abstract} 
    92 \begin{abstract}
    93 Algorithmic verification is an application of automated temporal reasoning based on model checking. Modal logics give us the power to specify system properties. System verification provides a correctness proof for the program design with respect to such properties. We apply methods, which are a composition of automata theory, graph theory and modal logics. This text is an introduction to the automata-theoretic constructions and space-efficient on-the-fly methods for the verification of reactive systems.
    94 \end{abstract}
    95 %\normalfont
    96 \newpage
    97 \section{Introduction}
    98 The rapid digital evolution of semi-conductor design has changed the way of development in the industry. Exponential growth in processing power has massive implications on the complexity of chip-design. When a considerable portion of the development cycle is dedicated to design validation, an increasingly high effort is invested in the realisation of efficient verification methods.
    99 
   100 The computer hardware industry has adapted to the rise of complexity by the application of automated design verification. Another natural consequence was the preference of standard, non-specialised hardware solutions accompanied by software implementations of the required functionality. Software systems have penetrated all industries, and increasingly so in high-demand and safety-critical application areas. Software programs e.g. provide high-demand server infrastructures for the Internet, control our air traffic and increase safety in motor traffic. When handling such critical systems, it becomes inevitable to verify the correctness of the software solutions. 
   101 
   102 Compared to hardware design, the highly dynamic properties of software components confront us with another state space explosion. Concurrent system designs increase the complexity of verification by some orders of magnitude; and concurrent applications have started to dominate recent software solutions, because we are closing the physical limits for single-core processor frequencies.
   103 
   104 Again, the industry is facing a \emph{validation crisis} \cite{ref:automated verification}, and formal verification methods are in high demand. Deductive, computer-supported verification techniques are an interesting digression, but may not be applicable in the validation of software systems of high complexity. Theories for algorithmic verification have existed for decades and recent successful applications have demonstrated their practical value.
   105 
   106 In this text, we provide an introduction to formal verification by means of algorithmic methods. Such an algorithmic approach is the base for automated verification procedures. We will concentrate on the validation of reactive programs, without any loss of the general applicability of the presented methods. Reactive systems are, in contrast to terminating programs, continuous processes. Once initiated, a reactive system persists in an active state, where it reacts to concurrent inputs with appropriate actions. Examples of reactive systems are monitoring processes, schedulers and even whole operating systems.
   107 
   108 The first three sections define the preliminaries for the automata-theoretic constructions. At first, we provide the notion of reasoning about infinite computational paths within formal language theory. Then we tackle those infinite structures with the help of automata theory, which builds the framework of the formal verification theory. Next we introduce the reader to modal logics, in particular to linear temporal logic. Linear temporal logic is the language we use to talk about system properties, i.e., the system specification language. 
   109 
   110 The fifth section interweaves automata theory and modal logics for the formalisation of the automata constructions, i.e., we construct automata depicting the program design and the specified properties. Based on this constructions, we apply the methods presented in the model checking section. The last section is a short excursion into the practical considerations of automated verification. For a successful application of automated verification, we consider ways of reducing the complexity of the automata-theoretic approach.
   111 
   112 The formal frame of this text is mostly based on Madhavan Mukund's \cite{ref:ltl&büchi} and Moshe Y. Vardi's \cite[C.17]{ref:handbook} work. We conclude this paper with a discussion of \cite{ref:ltl&büchi}.
   113 
   114 \section{$\omega$-regular languages}
   115 For the formalisation of non-terminating, reactive systems, we need to get familiar with the concept of infinity. When a system is persistently active, the conceptual model of its input becomes an infinite structure, and likewise the description of its computational path. We want to settle this infinite structures within a formal corset.
   116 
   117 \begin{def:finite words}
   118 Let $\Sigma$ be a non-empty set of symbols, called the alphabet. $\Sigma^*$ is the set of all \emph{finite} words over $\Sigma$. A \emph{finite} word $w \in \Sigma^*$ is a \emph{finite} sequence $(v_0,...,v_{n-1})$ of symbols from alphabet $\Sigma$ with length $n = |w|$. $\varepsilon$ denotes the empty word with length $|\varepsilon| = 0$.
   119 \end{def:finite words}
   120 
   121 \begin{def:regular languages}
   122 The class of regular languages is defined recursively over an alphabet $\Sigma$:
   123 \begin{multicols}{2}
   124 \begin{itemize}
   125 \item $\emptyset$ is regular
   126 \item $\{\varepsilon\}$ is regular
   127 \item $\forall_{a \in \Sigma}:\{a\}$ is regular
   128 \end{itemize}
   129 \end{multicols}
   130 \end{def:regular languages}
   131 
   132 \begin{def:regular languages closure}
   133 Let $L_{R_1}, L_{R_2} \in \Sigma^*$ be regular. The class of regular languages is closed under following operations:
   134 \begin{multicols}{2}
   135 \begin{itemize}
   136 \item $L_{R_1}^*$
   137 \item $L_{R_1} \circ L_{R_2}$
   138 \item $L_{R_1} \cup L_{R_2}$
   139 \item $L_{R_1} \cap L_{R_2}$
   140 \item $\overline{L}_{R_1}$ and therefore $L_{R_1} - L_{R_2}$
   141 \end{itemize}
   142 \end{multicols}
   143 \end{def:regular languages closure}
   144 
   145 \begin{def:infinite words}
   146 $\Sigma^\omega$ is the set of all \emph{infinite} words over $\Sigma$. An \emph{infinite} word $w \in \Sigma^\omega$ is an \emph{infinite} sequence $(v_0,...,v_\infty)$ with length $\infty$. To address the elements of the infinite sequence $w$, we view the word as a function $w : \N \to \Sigma$ with $w(i) = v_i$; thus $w(i)$ denotes the symbol at sequence position $i$ of word $w$; another notation used for $w(i)$ is $w_i$.
   147 \end{def:infinite words}
   148 
   149 \begin{def:omega regular languages}
   150 Set $L$ is an $\omega$-language over alphabet $\Sigma$ iff $L \subseteq \Sigma^\omega$. Let $L_R \subseteq \Sigma^*$ be a non-empty regular finite language and $\varepsilon \notin L_R$. A set $L$ is $\omega$-regular iff $L$ is an $\omega$-language and $L = L_R^\omega$.
   151 \end{def:omega regular languages}
   152 
   153 \begin{def:omega regular languages closure}
   154 Let $L_{\omega_1}, L_{\omega_2} \subseteq \Sigma^\omega$ be $\omega$-regular languages. The class of $\omega$-regular languages is closed under following operations:
   155 \begin{itemize}
   156 \item $L_R \circ L_{\omega_1}$, but \emph{not} $L_{\omega_1} \circ L_R$
   157 \item $L_{\omega_1} \cup L_{\omega_2}$, but only \emph{finitely} many times
   158 \end{itemize}
   159 \end{def:omega regular languages closure}
   160 
   161 \section{B\"uchi automata}
   162 Automata theory is the foundation of state-based modelling of computation. Non-deter\-ministic automata provide an elegant way of describing interleaving systems. B\"uchi automata extend the idea of such automata to comfort the need for computational models on infinite inputs.
   163 
   164 \begin{def:buechi automata}
   165 A non-deterministic B\"uchi automaton is a tuple $\A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$, where $\Sigma$ is a finite non-empty \emph{alphabet}, $S$ is a finite non-empty set of \emph{states}, $S_0 \subseteq S$ is the set of \emph{initial states}, $F \subseteq S$ is the set of \emph{accepting states} and $\Delta: S \times \Sigma \times S$ is a \emph{transition relation}. When suitable we will use the arrow notation for the transitions, where $s \xrightarrow{a} s'$ iff $(s, a, s') \in \Delta$.
   166 
   167 A \emph{deterministic B\"uchi automaton} is a specialisation, where the \emph{transition relation} $\Delta$ is a \emph{transition function} $\delta: S \times \Sigma \to S$ and the set $S_0$ of \emph{initial states} contains only a single state $s_0$.
   168 
   169 Within this text \emph{automaton} will refer to the non-deterministic B\"uchi automaton, unless otherwise noted. 
   170 \end{def:buechi automata}
   171 
   172 With infinite inputs comes a new definition of acceptance. Automata on finite inputs define acceptance by the termination of the computation in an accepting state. This notion needs adjustments, when modelling non-terminating systems. First, we need to define the legal sequence of state transitions of an automaton when reading an infinite input word.
   173 
   174 \begin{def:automata runs}
   175 Let $\A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$ be an automaton, a run $\rho$ of $\A$ on an infinite word $w = (a_0,a_1,...)$ over alphabet $\Sigma$ is a sequence $\rho = (s_0,s_1,...)$, where $s_0 \in S_0$ and $(s_i, a_i, s_{i+1}) \in \Delta$, for all $i \geq 0$. Again we may view the run sequence as a function $\rho : \N \to S$, where $\rho(i) = s_i$ denotes the state at the $i^{th}$ sequence position.
   176 \end{def:automata runs}
   177 
   178 \begin{def:automata acceptance}
   179 Let $\A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$ be an automaton and let $\rho$ be a run of $\A$, we define $inf(\rho) = \{s \in S \mid \exists^\omega{n \in \N}: \rho(n) = s\}$, where $\exists^\omega$ denotes the existential quantifier for infinitely many occurrences, i.e., $s$ occurs infinitely often in $\rho$.
   180 
   181 The run $\rho$ is \emph{accepting} iff $inf(\rho) \cap F \neq \emptyset$, i.e., there exists an \emph{accepting state} which occurs infinitely often in the run $\rho$. The automaton $\A$ \emph{accepts} an input word $w$, iff there exists a run $\rho$ of $\A$ on $w$, such that $\rho$ is \emph{accepting}. 
   182 
   183 The language $L_\omega(\A)$ recognised by automaton $\A$ is the set of all infinite words accepted by $\A$. A language $L$ is \emph{B\"uchi-recognisable} iff there is an automaton $\A$ with $L = L_\omega(\A)$. The class of B\"uchi-recognisable languages corresponds to the class of $\omega$-regular languages.
   184 \end{def:automata acceptance}
   185 
   186 Given all legal computations of an automaton, we have defined the acceptance condition. A computation is accepting, if it passes through an accepting state infinitely times. Since the set of states $S$ is finite, there must be a state $s \in S$, which occurs infinitely often within an infinite run; but it is not necessary, that $s$ is an accepting state; notice that $F$ can be an empty set.
   187 
   188 \subsection{Example}
   189 \label{ex:automaton}
   190 %\begin{figure}[h]
   191 \begin{wrapfigure}{r}{0.5\textwidth}
   192 \label{fig:automaton}
   193 \vspace{-22pt}
   194 %\centering
   195 \begin{center}
   196 \begin{tikzpicture}[shorten >=0pt, node distance=2cm, auto, semithick, >=stealth
   197     %every state/.style={fill, draw=none, gray, text=white},
   198     ,accepting/.style={fill, gray!50!black, text=white}
   199     %initial/.style ={gray, text=white}]%,  thick]
   200     ]
   201 %\draw[help lines] (0,0) grid (3,2);
   202 \node[state,initial, initial text=] (q_0) {$q_0$};
   203 \node[state] (q_1) [above right of= q_0] {$q_1$};
   204 \node[state,accepting](q_2) [below right of= q_1] {$q_2$};
   205 \path[->] 
   206 (q_0) edge node {$a$} (q_1)
   207   edge [loop above] node {$b$} ()
   208 (q_1) edge node {$b$} (q_2)
   209   edge [loop above] node {$a$} ()
   210 (q_2) %edge node {$a$} (q_1)
   211   edge node {$b$} (q_0);
   212 \draw[->] (q_2) .. controls +(up:1cm) and +(right:1cm) .. node[above] {$a$} (q_1);
   213 \end{tikzpicture}
   214 \end{center}
   215 \caption{B\"uchi automaton $\A_1$ (\ref{ex:automaton} Example)}
   216 \vspace{-42pt}
   217 %\end{figure}
   218 \end{wrapfigure}
   219 
   220 Let $\A_1 = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$ be an automaton with:
   221 \begin{itemize}
   222 \item $\Sigma = \{a, b\}$
   223 \item $S = \{q_0, q_1, q_2\}$
   224 \item $S_0 = \{q_0\}$
   225 \item $\Delta = \{(q_0, a, q_0), (q_0, b, q_0),$\\
   226 \hspace*{0.9cm}$(q_1, a, q_1), (q_1, b, q_2),$\\
   227 \hspace*{0.9cm}$(q_2, a, q_1), (q_2, b, q_0)\}$
   228 \item $F = \{q_2\}$
   229 \end{itemize}
   230 %
   231 Figure \ref{fig:automaton} shows $\A_1$, the initial state is marked with an unlabelled incoming arrow and the only accepting state $q_2$ is a filled circle.
   232 
   233 By some further investigation of the automaton, we identify the recognised language $L_\omega(\A_1)$ of the automaton, it is the set of all infinite words with infinitely many occurrences of the sequence $ab$.
   234 
   235 \subsection{Generalised B\"uchi automata}
   236 In the following two sections, we present the modal logic, which is used for the specification of system properties and automata construction on such specifications. To provide a more convenient link between linear temporal logic and B\"uchi automata, we introduce a slightly different formalisation of automata with an extended acceptance condition.
   237 
   238 \begin{def:general automata}
   239 A \emph{generalised B\"uchi automaton} is a tuple $\A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, \{F_i\}_{i < k})$ for $i \in \N$, where the \emph{accepting states} $F_i$ are composed within a finite set with $F_i \subseteq S$.
   240 \end{def:general automata}
   241 
   242 \begin{def:general acceptance}
   243 The acceptance condition is adjusted accordingly. A run $\rho$ of $\A$ is \emph{accepting} iff $\forall{i < k}: inf(\rho) \cap F_i \neq \emptyset$. 
   244 \end{def:general acceptance}
   245 
   246 \begin{prop:general equiv}
   247 Let $\A = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, \{F_i\}_{i < k})$ be a \emph{generalised automaton} and let $\A_i = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F_i)$ be \emph{non-deterministic automata}, then following equivalence condition holds:
   248 \[L_\omega(\A) = \bigcap_{i < k} L_\omega(\A_i)\]
   249 \end{prop:general equiv}
   250 \noindent The equivalence of the language recognition abilities of general and non-deterministic B\"uchi automata follows intuitively.
   251 
   252 \section{Linear temporal logic}
   253 %All arts and sciences interpret time in some way: historians prefer the past tense, while politicians make only promises for the future.
   254 Nothing escapes time, but time has successfully escaped its capture in computer science until the rise of the modal logics in the second half of the 20th century \cite[C.11]{ref:handbook}. Physicists know many time arrows, one of which constitutes the thermodynamic arrow of time, which happens to be the one we perceive by remembering the past and not the future. We compensate our inability to control the direction of time by the use of rigorous language constructs when reasoning about temporal events.
   255 
   256 When natural language fails in providing unambiguousness, we have to resort to formal languages. To handle discrete time, we use \emph{propositional logic} as the base and extend it by some more or less modal connectives. There are two major temporal logics used in the specification of system properties, \emph{linear temporal logic}, short LTL, and \emph{branching temporal logic}, short CTL -- for computation tree logic. Throughout this text, we will restrict our attention to linear temporal logic.
   257 
   258 \subsection{Syntax}
   259 Let $\Prop$ be the countable set of \emph{atomic propositions}. The \emph{alphabet} of the language $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$ is $\Prop \cup \{\neg, \lor, \X, \U\}$. We define the $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$-\emph{formulae} $\varphi$ using following productions:
   260 \[\varphi ::= p \in \Prop \,|\, \neg \varphi \,|\, \varphi \lor \varphi \,|\, \X \varphi \,|\, \varphi \U \varphi\]
   261 %
   262 The intuition should go as follows: $\neg$ and $\lor$ correspond to the Boolean \emph{negation} and \emph{disjunction}, the unary temporal operator $\X$ reads as \emph{next} and the binary temporal operator $\U$ reads as \emph{until}.
   263 \subsection{Semantics}
   264 Temporal logics are interpreted over computation paths; in LTL such a path depicts a linear sequence, where in CTL the path is a tree with branching connectives. In the interpretation of LTL over \emph{computation paths}, a computation corresponds to a model over a \emph{Kripke-frame} constructed by the order of natural numbers.
   265 
   266 \begin{def:frames}
   267 An LTL-\emph{frame} is a tuple $\F = (S, R)$, where $S = \{s_i \mid i \in \N\}$ is the set of states and $R = \{(s_i, s_{i+1}) \mid i \in \N\}$ the set of accessibility relations. Hence $S$ is an isomorphism of $\N$ and $R$ an isomorphism of the strict linear order $(\N, <)$, which corresponds to the linear progression of discrete time. 
   268 \end{def:frames}
   269 %
   270 \noindent The frame defines the structure of linear time and the flow temporal events. To perfect our structure for temporal reasoning, we need to give those events a formal meaning. We do so by assigning a value to each atomic proposition.
   271 
   272 \begin{def:models}
   273 An LTL-\emph{model} is a tuple $\M = (\F, V)$, where $\F$ is a \emph{frame} and $V: S \to 2^\Prop$ a \emph{valuation function}. Intuitively we say $p \in \Prop$ is \emph{true} at time instant $i$ iff $p \in V(i)$. 
   274 %A \emph{model} is a function $\M: \N \to 2^\Prop$ over \emph{frame} $\F$. The frame constitutes a linear order over $\N$, which corresponds to the linear progression of time from the \emph{present/past} into the \emph{future}. Therefore $\M(i)$ assigns a set of \emph{positive atomic propositions} to each state of time instant $i$. Intuitively we say $p \in \Prop$ is \emph{true} at time instant $i$ iff $p \in \M(i)$.
   275 \end{def:models}
   276 %
   277 \begin{def:satisfiability}
   278 A model $\M = (\F, V)$ \emph{satisfies} a formula $\varphi$ at time instant $i$ is denoted by $\M,i \models \varphi$. Satisfiability of a formula $\varphi$ is defined inductively over the structure of $\varphi$:
   279 \begin{itemize}
   280 \item $\M,i \models p$ for $p \in \Prop \iff p \in V(i)$
   281 \item $\M,i \models \neg \varphi \iff$ not $\M,i \models \varphi$
   282 \item $\M,i \models \varphi \lor \psi \iff \M,i \models \varphi$ or $\M,i \models \psi$
   283 \item $\M,i \models \X \varphi \iff \M,i+1 \models \varphi$
   284 \item $\M,i \models \varphi \U \psi \iff \exists{k \geq i}: \M,k \models \psi$ and $\forall{i \leq j < k}: \M,j \models\varphi$
   285 \end{itemize}
   286 \end{def:satisfiability}
   287 %
   288 \noindent From the strict linear order of the LTL-frame accessibility relation follows that an LTL-formula $\varphi$ is \emph{satisfiable}, iff there exists a model $\M$ with $\M,0 \models \varphi$.
   289 
   290 We clearly see, that atomic propositions, which are not contained within the formula $\varphi$ are redundant to the the definition of the satisfiability. By defining the \emph{vocabulary} of a formula, we dispose such irrelevant atomic proposition from the alphabet.
   291 
   292 \begin{def:vocabulary}
   293 Let $\varphi$ be an LTL-formula over atomic propositions $\Prop$, we define the \emph{vocabulary} $Voc(\varphi)$ of $\varphi$ inductively:
   294 \begin{multicols}{2}
   295 \begin{itemize}
   296 \item $Voc(p) = \{p\}$ for $p \in \Prop$
   297 \item $Voc(\neg \varphi) = Voc(\varphi)$
   298 \item $Voc(\varphi \lor \psi) = Voc(\varphi) \cup Voc(\psi)$
   299 \item $Voc(\X \varphi) = Voc(\varphi)$
   300 \item $Voc(\varphi \U \psi) = Voc(\varphi) \cup Voc(\psi)$
   301 \end{itemize}
   302 \end{multicols}
   303 %
   304 \noindent Let $\M = (\F, V)$ be a model and $\varphi$ an LTL-formula, we define model $\M_{Voc(\varphi)} = (\F, V_{Voc(\varphi)})$ with:
   305 \[\forall{i \in \N}: V_{Voc(\varphi)}(i) = V(i) \cap Voc(\varphi)\]
   306 Henceforth, we will abbreviate $\M_{Voc(\varphi)}$ and $V_{Voc(\varphi)}$ with $\M_\varphi$ and $V_\varphi$ accordingly. 
   307 %\noindent Let $\M$ be a model and $\varphi$ an LTL-formula, we define model $\M_{Voc(\varphi)}$:
   308 %\[\forall{i \in \N}: \M_{Voc(\varphi)} = \M(i) \cap Voc(\varphi)\]
   309 \end{def:vocabulary}
   310 %
   311 \begin{prop:vocabulary sat}
   312 Let $\M$ be a model and $\varphi$ an LTL-formula, then following holds:
   313 \[\forall{i \in \N}: \M,i \models \varphi \iff \M_\varphi,i \models \varphi\] 
   314 \end{prop:vocabulary sat}
   315 %
   316 \subsection{Derived connectives}
   317 \label{sec:derived connectives}
   318 For a more convenient description of system specifications, we present some derived symbols to be used in LTL-formulae. At first, we introduce the notion of \emph{truth} and \emph{falsity} using constants $\top$ and $\bot$. Then we expand our set of connectives with the Boolean \emph{and}, \emph{implication} and \emph{equivalence}. And at last we derive the commonly used modal operators \emph{eventually} and \emph{henceforth}. 
   319 
   320 In anticipation of section \ref{sec:on-the-fly methods}, we extend our logic's syntax with the binary connective $\V$, the dual of $\U$, which will become useful in the interpretation known as the \emph{two-state semantics}.
   321 
   322 Let $\varphi$ and $\psi$ be $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$-formulae:
   323 \begin{multicols}{2}
   324 \begin{itemize}
   325 \item $\top \equiv p \lor \neg p$ for $p \in \Prop$
   326 \item $\bot \equiv \neg \top$
   327 \item $\varphi \land \psi \equiv \neg (\neg \varphi \lor \neg \psi)$
   328 \item $\varphi \rightarrow \psi \equiv \neg \varphi \lor \psi$
   329 \item $\varphi \leftrightarrow \psi \equiv (\varphi \rightarrow \psi) \land (\psi \rightarrow \varphi)$
   330 \item $\Diamond \varphi \equiv \top \U \varphi$
   331 \item $\Box \varphi \equiv \neg \Diamond \neg \varphi$
   332 \item $\varphi \V \psi \equiv \neg(\neg \varphi \U \neg \psi)$
   333 \end{itemize}
   334 \end{multicols}
   335 \noindent From the derivations for operators $\Diamond$, \emph{read diamond}, and $\Box$, \emph{read box}, it follows:
   336 \begin{multicols}{2}
   337 \begin{itemize}
   338 \item $\M,i \models \Diamond \varphi \iff \exists{k \geq i}: \M,k \models \varphi$
   339 \item $\M,i \models \Box \varphi \iff \forall{k \geq i}: \M,k \models \varphi$
   340 \end{itemize}
   341 \end{multicols}
   342 
   343 \noindent With the additional derived connectives we get the following $L_{LTL}(\Prop)$-formulae productions:
   344 \[\varphi ::= p \in \Prop \,|\, \neg \varphi \,|\, \varphi \lor \varphi \,|\, \varphi \land \varphi \,|\, \X \varphi \,|\, \varphi \U \varphi \,|\, \varphi \rightarrow \varphi \,|\, \varphi \leftrightarrow \varphi \,|\, \Diamond \varphi \,|\, \Box \varphi\]
   345 
   346 \section{Automata construction}
   347 Before applying the automata-theoretic verification methods, we need to construct the automaton for a given specification formula $\varphi$ and for the program $P$ in test.
   348 
   349 \subsection{Specification automata}
   350 \label{sec:specification automata}
   351 For the construction of an automaton $\A_\varphi$ for an LTL-formula $\varphi$, we treat the model $\M = (\F, V)$ for an LTL-formula $\varphi$ as an infinite word over the finite alphabet $2^{Voc(\varphi)}$. 
   352 
   353 \begin{def:rep function}
   354 We define the \emph{representation function} $rep: \M \to 2^\Prop$, which returns an infinite word representing the model $\M_\varphi = (\F, V_\varphi)$ over the ordered image $V_\varphi^\rightarrow(\N)$ of its validation function, i.e., $rep(\M_\varphi) = (V_\varphi(0), V_\varphi(1), ...)$. Additionally, we provide the \emph{inverted representation function} $rep^{-1}: 2^\Prop \to \M$, which compiles an infinite word to the corresponding model, i.e., $rep^{-1}(V_\varphi^\rightarrow(\N)) = \M_\varphi$.
   355 \[Mod(\varphi) = \{rep(\M_\varphi) \mid \M_\varphi = (\F, V_\varphi) \land \M_\varphi,0 \models \varphi\}\]
   356 $Mod(\varphi)$ is the set of all infinite words, which represent models for $\varphi$.
   357 \end{def:rep function}
   358 
   359 \begin{def:fs closure}
   360 \label{def:fs closure}
   361 Let $\varphi$ be an LTL-formula, then the \emph{Fischer-Ladner closure} $CL(\varphi)$ of $\varphi$ is the smallest set of formulae such that following holds:
   362 %\begin{multicols}{2}
   363 \begin{itemize}
   364 \begin{multicols}{2}
   365 \item $\varphi \in CL(\varphi)$
   366 \item $\neg \psi \in CL(\varphi) \implies \psi \in CL(\varphi)$
   367 \item $\psi \in CL(\varphi) \implies \neg \psi \in CL(\varphi)$
   368 \item $\psi \lor \chi \in CL(\varphi) \implies \psi, \chi \in CL(\varphi)$
   369 \item $\X \psi \in CL(\varphi) \implies \psi \in CL(\varphi)$
   370 \item $\psi \V \chi \in CL(\varphi) \implies \psi, \chi \in CL(\varphi)$
   371 \end{multicols}
   372 \vspace{-1.1em}
   373 \item $\psi \U \chi \in CL(\varphi) \implies \psi, \chi, \X(\psi \U \chi) \in CL(\varphi)$
   374 \end{itemize}
   375 %\end{multicols}
   376 \end{def:fs closure}
   377 
   378 \noindent Let $CL(\varphi)$ be the closure of formula $\varphi$, we define a subset with the \emph{until}-formulae of the closure $\mathbb{U}_\varphi \subseteq CL(\varphi)$ where:
   379 \[\mathbb{U}_\varphi = \{\psi \U \chi \mid \psi \U \chi \in CL(\varphi)\} \text{ and } \mathbb{U}_{\varphi_i} \text{ denotes the $i^{th}$ element of } \mathbb{U_\varphi}\]
   380 
   381 \begin{def:atoms}
   382 Let $\varphi$ be a formula and $CL(\varphi)$ its closure. $A \subseteq CL(\varphi)$ is an \emph{atom} if following holds:
   383 \begin{itemize}
   384 \item $\forall{\psi \in CL(\varphi)}: \psi \in A \iff \neg \psi \notin A$
   385 \item $\forall{\psi \lor \chi \in CL(\varphi)}: \psi \lor \chi \in A \iff \psi \in A$ or $\chi \in A$ 
   386 \item $\forall{\psi \U \chi \in CL(\varphi)}: \psi \U \chi \in A \iff \chi \in A$ or $\psi, \X(\psi \U \chi) \in A$ 
   387 \end{itemize}
   388 We define the set of all atoms of formula $\varphi$ with $\mathbb{AT}_\varphi = \{A \subseteq CL({\varphi}) \mid A \text{ is an atom}\}$.
   389 \end{def:atoms}
   390 
   391 \noindent Now that we have the required ingredients, we begin with the construction of automaton $\A_\varphi$ for formula $\varphi$. Let $\A_\varphi = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, \{F_i\})$ with:
   392 \begin{itemize}
   393 \item $\Sigma = 2^{Voc(\varphi)}$
   394 \item $S = \mathbb{AT_\varphi}$
   395 \item $S_0 = \{A \in \mathbb{AT_\varphi} \mid \varphi \in A\}$
   396 %\item $(A, P, B) \in \Delta$ for $A, B \in \mathbb{AT_\varphi}$ and $P = A \cap Voc(\varphi) \iff (\X \psi \in A \iff \psi \in B)$
   397 \item $\Delta = \{(A, P, B) \mid A, B \in \mathbb{AT_\varphi}, P = A \cap Voc(\varphi), \X \psi \in A \iff \psi \in B\}$
   398 %\item $\forall{i \in \N, i < k = |\mathbb{U}_{CL(\varphi)}|}: F_i = \{A \in \mathbb{AT}_\varphi \mid \psi \U \chi \notin A$ or $\chi \in A\}$
   399 \item $F_i = \{A \in \mathbb{AT}_\varphi \mid \psi \U \chi = \mathbb{U}_{\varphi_i}, \psi \U \chi \notin A$ or $\chi \in A\}$
   400 %Let $A, B \in \mathbb{AT}$ and $P \subseteq Voc(\varphi)$. Then $(A, P, B) \in \Delta$ iff the following holds:
   401 %$P = A \cap Voc(\varphi)$ and For all $\X \psi \in CL(\varphi): \X \psi \in A$ iff $\psi \in B$.
   402 \end{itemize}
   403 
   404 \begin{thm:model language}
   405 \label{thm:model language}
   406 Let $\M_\varphi = (\F, V_\varphi)$ be a model and $rep(\M_\varphi)$ its infinite representation word, then following holds:
   407 \[rep(\M_\varphi) \in L_\omega(\A_\varphi) \iff \M_\varphi,0 \models \varphi\]
   408 \end{thm:model language}
   409 \noindent
   410 \begin{proof}
   411 For the elaborate proof, consult \cite{ref:ltl&büchi}.
   412 \end{proof}
   413 \begin{cor:mod=model language}
   414 \label{cor:mod=model language}
   415 From Theorem \ref{thm:model language} follows $Mod(\varphi) = L_\omega(\A_\varphi)$.
   416 \end{cor:mod=model language}
   417 
   418 \subsection{Program automata}
   419 In the next step, we model a given program $P$ as automaton $\A_P$. A program is a structure $P = (S_P, s_0, R, V)$, where $S$ is the set of possible states of the program, $s_0$ the initial state, $R : S \times \Prop \times S$ the transition relation and $V : S \to 2^\Prop$ a valuation function. A \emph{computation} of $P$ is a run $\rho = (V(s_0), V(s_1), ...)$. 
   420 
   421 We construct automaton $\A_P = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$, with:
   422 \begin{itemize}
   423 \begin{multicols}{2}
   424 \item $\Sigma = 2^\Prop$
   425 \item $S = S_P$
   426 \item $S_0 = \{s_0\}$
   427 \item $F = S$
   428 \end{multicols}
   429 \vspace{-1.1em}
   430 \item $\Delta = \{(s, V(s), s') \mid \exists{a \in \Prop}: (s, a, s') \in R\}$
   431 \end{itemize}
   432 In practical verification of programs, the specification covers only the properties of a system, which are vital to the program's correctness, where our program description contains all details of all possible execution paths. Let $\varphi$ be the specification formula, we can reduce the state exploration to the vocabulary of $\varphi$ by the reduction of the transition relation to $\Delta = \{(s, A, s') \mid \exists{a \in \Prop}: (s, a, s') \in R \land A = V(s) \cap Voc(\varphi)\}$.
   433 
   434 \begin{prop:computation set=language}
   435 \label{prop:computation set=language}
   436 Let $\A_P = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, F)$, for $F = S$ it follows that each run of $\A_P$ is accepting, therefore is $L_\omega(\A_P)$ the set of all computations of $P$.
   437 \[L_\omega(\A_P) = \{\rho \mid \rho \text{ is a run of } \A_P\}\]
   438 \end{prop:computation set=language}
   439 
   440  We can view each run of $\A_P$, i.e., each computation of $P$, as a representation of model $\M_\rho = (\F, V)$, where $\F$ is a frame and $V$ the program's valuation function. In analogy to the specification, we define:
   441 \[Mod(P) = \{\rho \mid \rho \text{ is a computation of } P\}\]
   442 \begin{cor:mod=program language}
   443 \label{cor:mod=program language}
   444 From Theorem \ref{thm:model language} and Proposition \ref{prop:computation set=language} follows $Mod(P) = L_\omega(\A_P)$.
   445 \end{cor:mod=program language}
   446 
   447 \section{Model checking}
   448 For effective automata-theoretic verification of reactive programs, we have modeled the program as a non-deterministic B\"uchi automaton $\A_P$ and the specification formula $\varphi$ as automaton $\A_\varphi$. 
   449 
   450 Given a program $P$ and specification $\varphi$, the verification problem is the following: \emph{does every run of $P$ satisfy $\varphi$?} To show this we use the previously introduced automata constructions and reduce the problem to $L_\omega(\A_P) \subseteq L_\omega(\A_\varphi)$, i.e., all runs accepted by $\A_P$ are also accepted by $\A_\varphi$. By this problem definition, we clearly have to explore the whole state space of $\A_\varphi$ for each run of $\A_P$. This prevents efficient on-demand constructions. Therefore we rephrase the problem with the contra-positive definition $L_\omega(\A_P) \cap \overline{L_\omega(\A_\varphi)} = \emptyset$, where $\overline{L_\omega(\A_\varphi)} = \Sigma^\omega - L_\omega(\A_\varphi) = L_\omega(\A_{\neg \varphi})$ \cite{ref:alternating verification}.
   451 
   452 In conclusion, the essence of model checking lies within the test for emptiness of the intersection between the recognised language of the program automaton and the recognised language of the automaton for its negated specification:
   453 \[L_\omega(\A_P) \cap L_\omega(\A_{\neg \varphi}) = \emptyset\]
   454 
   455 \begin{thm:model checking}
   456 \label{thm:model checking}
   457 Let $P$ be a finite-state program and $\A_P$ its automaton, let $\varphi$ be an LTL-formula and $\A_\varphi$ its automaton. P satisfies $\varphi$ iff $L_\omega(\A_P) \cap L_\omega(\A_{\neg \varphi}) = \emptyset$.
   458 \end{thm:model checking}
   459 
   460 \noindent From Corollary \ref{cor:mod=model language} and \ref{cor:mod=program language} follows:
   461 \[L_\omega(\A_P) \cap L_\omega(\A_{\neg \varphi}) = \emptyset \iff Mod(P) \cap Mod(\neg \varphi) = \emptyset\]
   462 
   463 \subsection{Complexity}
   464 Let the size $|P|$ of a program $P = (S, s_0, R, V)$ be proportional to the sum of its structural components, i.e., $|P| = |S| + |R|$. The size $|\varphi|$ is the length of the formula string. The asymptotic complexity of the presented automata-theoretic verification method is in time $O(|P| \cdot 2^{O(|\varphi|)})$ \cite{ref:concurrent checking}. 
   465 
   466 The size of $\varphi$ is usually short \cite{ref:concurrent checking}, so the exponential growth by it is reasonable. Generally, the number of states is at least exponential in the size of its description by means of a programming language. This concludes: despite that the upper bound is polynomial in the size of the program, in practice, we are facing exponential growth in complexity \cite[C.17]{ref:handbook}.
   467 
   468 \section{On-the-fly methods}
   469 \label{sec:on-the-fly methods}
   470 The automata-theoretic approach on verification in Theorem \ref{thm:model checking} requires a fully constructed automaton for the specification, when applying the graph-theoretic emptiness test. 
   471 
   472 A more space-efficient strategy is the on-the-fly construction of the automaton during a depth-first search, short DFS. The DFS explores the product states of both automata incrementally, testing for cycles in each iteration. If the program does not satisfy a formula, an accepting cycle will occur and lead to termination of the search. In the case of a valid program, i.e., the program does meet the specification, no cycles will occur. In the latter case, such a strategy would inevitably explore the whole state space of the automata.
   473 
   474 \subsection{Two-state semantics}
   475 A new interpretation for the infinite computation paths will help us in the incremental construction of automata. We separate the computation paths in two states by applying temporal reasoning; and we do so incrementally for each time instant. The two states resemble the satisfiability requirements for any time instant $i$ and its successor $i+1$.
   476 
   477 \subsubsection{Example}
   478 Let $\varphi = a \U b$. We apply the two-state semantics on $\varphi$ and it follows:
   479 \[\forall{i \in \N}: \M,i \models \varphi \iff \M,i \models b \text{ or } \M,i+1 \models a \land \X(\varphi)\]
   480 In this example, we construct the specification automaton incrementally for each time instant; the states are constructed from the union of the current-state and next-state requirements $\{b\} \cup \{a, \X(\varphi)\}$.
   481 
   482 Let us formalise the notion of the incremental automaton construction based on the idea of the two-state semantics.
   483 
   484 \begin{def:positive formulae}
   485 Let $\Prop$ be a set of atomic propositions and let $\overline{\Prop} = \{\neg p \mid p \in \Prop\}$. We define the set of LTL-formulae in \emph{positive form}:
   486 \[\Phi^+ = \Prop \cup \overline{\Prop} \cup \{\top, \bot\} \cup \{\varphi \lor \psi, \varphi \land \psi, \X\varphi, \varphi \U \psi, \varphi \V \psi \mid \varphi, \psi \in \Phi^+\} \]
   487 \end{def:positive formulae}
   488 
   489 The positive form of a formula contains only negations at the level of atomic propositions. This is the reason for the introduction of the dual $\V$ in \ref{sec:derived connectives}; to provide a way of shifting the negation of $\U$-formulae inwards by the substitution with its contra-positive form. 
   490 
   491 \begin{def:next}
   492 Let $\Phi$ be a set of LTL-formulae, we define:
   493 \[next(\Phi) = \{ \X\varphi \mid \X\varphi \in \Phi\} \text{ and } snext(\Phi) = \{ \varphi \mid \X\varphi \in \Phi\}\]
   494 \end{def:next}
   495 
   496 \begin{def:dnf}
   497 Let $\Phi^+$ be the set of LTL-formulae in positive form and let $Q = \Prop \cup \overline{\Prop} \cup next(\Phi^+)$. We define the function $\dnf: \Phi^+ \to 2^Q$ inductively:
   498 \begin{align*}
   499 &\dnf(\top) &=  &\, \{\emptyset\}\\
   500 &\dnf(\bot) &= &\, \emptyset\\
   501 &\dnf(x) &=  &\, \{\{x\}\}, \text{ for } x = p, \neg p, \X\varphi\\
   502 &\dnf(\varphi \lor \psi) &=  &\, \dnf(\varphi) \cup \dnf(\psi)\\
   503 &\dnf(\varphi \land \psi) &=  &\, \{C \cup D \mid C \in \dnf(\varphi), D \in \dnf(\psi), C \cup D \text{ is consistent}\}\\
   504 &\dnf(\varphi \U \psi) &=  &\, \dnf(\varphi \land \X(\varphi \U \psi)) \cup \dnf(\psi)\\
   505 &\dnf(\varphi \V \psi) &=  &\, \dnf(\varphi \land \psi) \cup \dnf(\psi \land \X(\varphi \V \psi))
   506 \end{align*}
   507 \end{def:dnf}
   508 \noindent The disjunctive normal form provides the partitioning for the automata state construction over the two-state semantics. The modal connectives $\U$ and $\V$ are interpreted as disjunctions over the path of computation.
   509 
   510 \begin{lem:dnf}
   511 Let $\Phi^+$ be the set of formulae in positive form and let $\M_\varphi$ be a model over the vocabulary of $\varphi$ then following holds:
   512 \[\forall{\varphi \in \Phi^+}: \M_\varphi,0 \models \varphi \iff \M_\varphi,0 \models \bigvee_{D \in \dnf(\varphi)} \bigwedge D\]
   513 \end{lem:dnf}
   514 
   515 \begin{def:consq}
   516 Let $C \subseteq CL(\varphi)$, then $\consq(C)$ is the smallest subset of $CL(\varphi)$ such that following holds:
   517 \begin{itemize}
   518 %\begin{tabular}{ll}
   519 \begin{multicols}{2}
   520 \item $C \subseteq \consq(C)$
   521 \item $\top \in \consq(C)$, if $\top \in CL(\varphi)$
   522 \end{multicols}
   523 \vspace{-1em}
   524 \item $\psi \lor \chi \in \consq(C)$, if $\psi \lor \chi \in CL(\varphi)$ and $\psi \in \consq(C) \lor \chi \in \consq(C)$
   525 \item $\psi \land \chi \in \consq(C)$, if $\psi \land \chi \in CL(\varphi)$ and $\psi, \chi \in \consq(C)$
   526 \item $\psi \U \chi \in \consq(C)$, if $\psi \U \chi \in CL(\varphi)$ and $\psi, \X(\psi \U \chi) \in \consq(C) \lor \chi \in \consq(C)$
   527 \item $\psi \V \chi \in \consq(C)$, if $\psi \V \chi \in CL(\varphi)$ and $\psi, \X(\psi \U \chi) \in \consq(C) \lor \psi, \chi \in \consq(C)$
   528 %\end{tabular}
   529 \end{itemize}
   530 \end{def:consq}
   531 
   532 \begin{lem:consq}
   533 Let $\psi \in CL(\varphi)$, let $C, D \subseteq CL(\varphi)$ and let $\M$ be a model, then following holds:
   534 \begin{itemize}
   535 \begin{multicols}{2}
   536 \item $\consq(C) \subseteq \consq(D)$, if $C \subseteq D$
   537 \item $\psi \in \consq(C)$, if $C \in \dnf(\psi)$
   538 \item $\psi \in \consq(D)$, if $\psi \in C \land D \in \dnf(\bigwedge C)$
   539 \item $\M,0 \models \bigwedge \consq(C)$, if $\M,0 \models \bigwedge C$
   540 \end{multicols}
   541 \end{itemize}
   542 \end{lem:consq}
   543 
   544 \begin{def:partial automata}
   545 Let $\varphi$ be a formula with its disjunctive normal form $\dnf(\varphi)$ and let $Q = \Prop \cup \overline{\Prop} \cup next(CL(\varphi))$. Again we use the subset $\mathbb{U}_\varphi \subseteq CL(\varphi)$ of \emph{until}-formulae of the closure as defined in \ref{def:fs closure}. We define the \emph{partial automaton} $\A_\varphi = (\Sigma, S, S_0, \Delta, \{F_i\})$ with:
   546 \begin{itemize}
   547 \item $\Sigma = 2^{Voc(\varphi)}$
   548 \item $S = 2^Q$
   549 \item $S_0 = \dnf(\varphi)$
   550 \item $\Delta = \{(A, P, B) \mid \A \cap \Prop \subseteq P$ and $\{p \mid \neg p \in A\} \cap P = \emptyset$ and $B \in \dnf(\bigwedge snext(A)) \}$
   551 \item $F_i = \{A \in S \mid \psi \U \chi = \mathbb{U}_{\varphi_i}$ and $\psi \U \chi \notin \consq(A) \lor \chi \in \consq(A) \}$
   552 \end{itemize}
   553 \end{def:partial automata}
   554 
   555 \noindent The soundness and completeness proofs are provided in \cite{ref:ltl&büchi}; the equivalence of the partial automata and the specification automata as defined in \ref{sec:specification automata} follows from the proofs.  
   556 
   557 \subsection{On-the-fly construction}
   558 The sequential description of the program design makes it trivial to incrementally construct the program automaton state by state. The more difficult part is the construction of the partial specification automaton on-the-fly. 
   559 
   560 To archive this, we begin with a set of states built by applying $\dnf(\varphi)$. In the next step we determine a state within the current set of states, which is consistent with the program automaton. We use this state to expand its successor states. Now, we analyse the expanded state space for cycles. If no cycles are detected, we repeat this procedure, while there are still consistent states left. 
   561 
   562 When the procedure terminates, we check whether the specification automaton was fully built. If that is the case, we have explored the whole state space of both automata and have not found any cycles, i.e., the program does satisfy the specification. Otherwise, the procedure was prematurely aborted by a cycle detection, i.e., the program does satisfy the \emph{negated} specification and therefore does \emph{not} meet the specification properties. 
   563 
   564 \begin{algorithm}
   565 \caption{expand: $\Phi^+ \times 2^Q \to 2^Q$}
   566 \label{alg:expand}
   567 \begin{algorithmic}
   568 \REQUIRE $Node : node, NodeSet: set\, of\, nodes$
   569 \STATE $ExpandedNodes = \dnf(\bigwedge snext(Node)) - NodeSet$
   570 \RETURN $ExpandedNodes$
   571 \end{algorithmic}
   572 \end{algorithm}
   573 
   574 \begin{algorithm}
   575 \caption{verify: $\A \times L_{LTL}(\Prop) \to Boolean$}
   576 \label{alg:create}
   577 \begin{algorithmic}
   578 \REQUIRE $\A_P: automaton, \varphi: formula$
   579 \STATE $S = \dnf(\varphi)$
   580 %\WHILE {$Mod(\bigvee_{s \in S} \bigwedge s) \cap Mod(\A_P) = \emptyset$}
   581 \WHILE {$consistent(S, \A_P) \neq \emptyset \land \neg cycle(S, \A_P)$}
   582 \STATE $Node \in consistent(S, \A_P)$
   583 \STATE $S = S \cup expand(Node, S)$
   584 \ENDWHILE
   585 \RETURN $\neg complete(S, \varphi)$
   586 \end{algorithmic}
   587 \end{algorithm}
   588 
   589 \section*{Discussion}
   590 \emph{Linear-Time Temporal Logic and B\"uchi Automata} \cite{ref:ltl&büchi} is an in-depth introduction to automated verification. It delivers the core concepts of model checking in a comprehensible way. The formal proofs are clean and well absorbable. The referenced material effectively fills the gaps, when looking for more detailed explanations, e.g. about the on-the-fly method. Some few, but good examples support the substantiation of the theoretic material. The introduction section provides a good overview of the text structure and the basic theory behind most concepts used. 
   591 
   592 However, the author does not make an effort to deliver a motivation for the topic. From the beginning, the substance of the text resides within the context of model checking. Without an external view on the practical applications, the significance of formal verification to the industry remains unclear.
   593 
   594 A few definitions are either lacking formality or are inconsistent. It seems like several concepts are introduced ad-hoc and without rigor. In an introductory text, such inaccuracies may lead to confusion and divert the reader's attention from the essence of the presented topic.
   595 
   596 \begin{thebibliography}{99}
   597 \bibitem{ref:ltl&büchi} 
   598 \uppercase{M{\footnotesize adhavan} M{\footnotesize ukund}.}
   599 {\em Linear-Time Temporal Logic and B\"uchi Automata}.
   600 Winter School on Logic and Computer Science, Indian Statistical Institute, Calcutta, 1997.
   601 
   602 \bibitem{ref:alternating verification} 
   603 \uppercase{M{\footnotesize oshe} Y. V{\footnotesize ardi}.}
   604 {\em Alternating Automata and Program Verification}.
   605 Computer Science Today, Volume 1000 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1995.
   606 
   607 \bibitem{ref:automated verification} 
   608 \uppercase{M{\footnotesize oshe} Y. V{\footnotesize ardi}.}
   609 {\em Automated Verification: Graphs, Logic and Automata}.
   610 Proceeding of the International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Acapulco, 2003.
   611 
   612 \bibitem{ref:on-the-fly verification} 
   613 \uppercase{R{\footnotesize ob} G{\footnotesize erth,}  D{\footnotesize oron} P{\footnotesize eled,} M{\footnotesize oshe} Y. V{\footnotesize ardi and} P{\footnotesize ierre} W{\footnotesize olper}.}
   614 {\em Simple On-the-fly Automatic Verification of Linear Temporal Logic}.
   615 Proceeding IFIO/WG6.1 Symposium on Protocol Specification, Testing and Verification, Warsaw, 1995.
   616 
   617 \bibitem{ref:concurrent checking}
   618 \uppercase{O{\footnotesize rna} L{\footnotesize ichtenstein and} A{\footnotesize mir} P{\footnotesize nueli}.}
   619 {\em Checking that finite state concurrent programs satisfy their linear specification}.
   620 Proceeding 12th ACM Symposium on Principles of Programming Languages, New York, 1985.
   621 
   622 \bibitem{ref:infpaths}
   623 \uppercase{P{\footnotesize ierre} W{\footnotesize olper}, 
   624 M{\footnotesize oshe} Y. V{\footnotesize ardi and}
   625 A. P{\footnotesize rasad} S{\footnotesize istla}.}
   626 {\em Reasoning about Infinite Computation Paths}.
   627 Proceedings of the 24th IEEE FOCS, 1983.
   628 
   629 \bibitem{ref:handbook} 
   630 \uppercase{P{\footnotesize atrick} B{\footnotesize lackburn}, 
   631 F{\footnotesize rank} W{\footnotesize olter and} J{\footnotesize ohan van} B{\footnotesize enthem}.}
   632 {\em Handbook of Modal Logic (Studies in Logic and Practical Reasoning)}.
   633 3rd Edition, Elsevier, Amsterdam, Chapter 11 P. 655-720 and Chapter 17 P. 975-989, 2007.
   634 \end{thebibliography}
   635 \end{document}